You are currently browsing the tag archive for the ‘Axiom of Extension’ tag.
We encounter sets, or if we prefer, collections of objects, everyday in our lives. A herd of cattle, a group of women, or a bunch of yahoos are all instances of sets of living beings. “The mathematical concept of a set can be used as the foundation for all known mathematics.” The purpose here is to develop the basic properties of sets. As a slight digression, I wouldn’t consider myself a Platonist; hence, I don’t believe there are some abstract properties of sets “out there” and that the chief purpose of mathematics is to discover those abstract things, so to speak. Even though the idea of a set is ubiquitous and it seems like the very concept of a set is “external” to us, I still think that we must build, or rather postulate, the existence of the fundamental properties of sets. (I think I am more of a quasi-empiricist.)
Now, we won’t define what a set is, just as we don’t define what points or lines are in the familiar axiomatic approach to elementary geometry. So, we somewhat rely on our intuition to develop a definition of sets. Of course, our intuition may go wrong once in a while, but one of the very purposes of our exposition is to reason very clearly about our intuitive ideas, so that we can correct them any time if we discover they are wrong.
Now, a very reasonable thing to “expect” from a set is it should have elements or members. So, for example, Einstein was a member of the set of all the people who lived in the past. In mathematics, a line has points as its members, and a plane has lines as its members. The last example is a particularly important one for it underscores the idea that sets can be members of other sets!
So, a way to formalize the above notion is by developing the concept of belonging. This is a primitive (undefined) concept in axiomatic set theory. If is a member of
(
is contained in
, or
is an element of
), we write
. (
is a derivation of the Greek letter epsilon,
, introduced by Peano in 1888.) If
is not an element of
, we write
. Note that we generally reserve lowercase letters (
, etc) for members or elements of a set, and we use uppercase letters to denote sets.
A possible relation between sets, more elementary than belonging, is equality. If two sets and
are equal, we write
If two sets
and
are not equal, we write
Now, the most basic property of belonging is its relation to equality, which brings us to the following formulation of our first axiom of set theory.
Axiom of extension: Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same elements.
Let us examine the relation between equality and belonging a little more deeply. Suppose we consider human beings instead of sets, and change our definition of belonging a little. If and
are human beings, we write
whenever
is an ancestor of
. Then our new (or analogous) axiom of extension would say if two human beings
and
are equal then they have the same ancestors (this is the “only if” part, and it is certainly true), and also that if
and
have the same ancestors, then they are equal (this is the “if” part, and it certainly is false.)
and
could be two sisters, in which case they have the same ancestors but they are certainly not the same person.
Conclusion: The axiom of extension is not just a logically necessary property of equality but a non-trivial statement about belonging.
Also, note that the two sets and
have the same elements, and hence, by the axiom of extension,
, even though it seems like
has just two elements while
has five! It is due to this that we drop duplicates while writing down the elements of a set. So, in the above example, it is customary to simply write
.
Now, we come to the definition of a subset. Suppose and
are sets. If every member of
is a member of
, then we say
is a subset of
, or
includes
, and write
or
. This definition, clearly, implies that every set
is a subset of itself, i.e.
, which demonstrates the reflexive property of set inclusion. (Of course, equality also satisfies the reflexive property, i.e.
.) We say
is a proper subset of
whenever
but
. Now, if
and
, then
, which demonstrates the transitive property of set inclusion. (Once again, equality also satisfies this property, i.e. if
and
, then
.) However, we note that set inclusion doesn’t satisfy the symmetric property. This means, if
, then it doesn’t necessarily imply
. (On the other hand, equality satisfies the symmetric property, i.e. if
, then
.)
But, set inclusion does satisfy one very important property: the antisymmetric one. If we have and
, then
and
have the same elements, and therefore, by the axiom of extension,
. In fact, we can reformulate the axiom of extension as follows:
Axiom of extension(another version): Two sets
and
are equal if and only if
and
.
In mathematics, the above is almost always used whenever we are required to prove that two sets and
are equal. All we do is show that
and
, and invoke the (above version of) axiom of extension to conclude that
.
Before we conclude, we note that conceptually belonging () and set inclusion (
) are two different things.
always holds, but
is “false”; at least, it isn’t true of any reasonable set that anyone has ever constructed! This means, unlike set inclusion, belonging does not satisfy the reflexive property. Again, unlike set inclusion, belonging does not satisfy the transitive property. For example, a person could be considered a member of a country and a country could be considered a member of the United Nations Organizations (UNO); however, a person is not a member of the UNO.
Recent Comments